Dichiarazione Di Helsinki

download Dichiarazione Di Helsinki

of 2

Transcript of Dichiarazione Di Helsinki

  • 7/26/2019 Dichiarazione Di Helsinki

    1/2

    The 50thAnniversary of the Declarationof

    Helsinki

    Progress butManyRemaining Challenges

    Since 1964, through7 revisions, theWorldMedicalAs-

    sociations(WMAs)Declarationof Helsinkihas stood as

    an important statement regarding the ethical prin-

    ciples guiding medical research with human partici-

    pants.Thedeclarationisconsultedbyethicsreviewcom-

    mittees,funders, researchers,and research participants;

    has been incorporated into national legislation; and is

    routinely invoked to ascertain the ethical appropriate-

    ness of clinical trials.

    There is much to praiseaboutthe revision process

    and the latestrevision, which coincides with the decla-

    rations 50th anniversary. The Working Group exten-

    sively consulted stakeholders and justified the pro-

    posed revisions. Theresult is a declarationthat is better

    organized intoclearsections,more precise,and likely to

    be more effective at protecting research participants.

    Forthe firsttime,the declarationrequirescompen-

    sationand treatmentfor research-relatedinjuries(para-

    graph 15), an explicit recognition that research partici-

    pantsshould notbearthecostsof research gone wrong.1

    The revised declarations emphasis on the dissemina-

    tionof research results, includingstudieswith negative

    results, should increase the value of medical research

    (paragraphs23, 35, and36).

    Nevertheless, theproposed declarationcontainsper-

    sistent flaws.Whilethedocumentpurportsto bea state-

    mentof enduring ethical principles, thenearly continu-

    ous processof revisionundermines its authority.2

    More-over, thedeclarationcontinuesto assertthat consistent

    with themandate of theWMA, itsprimary audience is

    physicians (paragraph 2).This is a mistake.Indeed, the

    documentthenoffersrecommendationsforotherhealth

    professionals (paragraph9), research ethicscommittees

    (paragraph 23),sponsors andgovernments(paragraph

    34),andeditorsand publishers (paragraph36). Itis time

    fortheWMAtorecognizethattheDeclarationofHelsinki

    shouldaddressphysicians aswell other healthprofession-

    als and personnel involved in research. A statement of

    ethical principles does notrequire a mandate from the

    people who ought to follow those principles.2

    Thereviseddeclarationstreatmentof informedcon-sentremainsinadequate.It fails to recognize the possi-

    bilityof waivingconsentforsomeresearchinvolvingcom-

    petentadults,eventhoughsuchresearchiscommonand

    widely endorsed. Similarly, the declaration avoids pro-

    vidingguidance onwhenit canbe appropriateto askpar-

    ticipants togivebroadconsent fortheirbiologicalsamples

    tobe used in a wide rangeof futurestudies, rather than

    seeking consent for each specific study. This is a press-

    ingissueonwhichresearchersneedclearguidance.Inad-

    dition,the declarationprohibitsindividualswho cannot

    consentfrom participating inresearchthatdoes notad-

    dress the condition that caused their incapacity (para-

    graph30),evenwhentheresearchoffersparticipantsthe

    potential for important medical benefit and there are

    noorfewpotential participants whocan consent.This

    approachtransformsa protection into a barrier.

    ProblemsWithResearchPosingNetRisks

    Research studiesand interventionsthat poseriskswith-

    out compensating benefits to participantsnonben-

    eficialstudiesarecrucialtoimprovingmedicalcare.Yet

    the revised declaration offers conflicting and problem-

    atic guidance on this topic. It rejects placing partici-

    pantsatanynetrisktocollectdata,nomatterhowvalu-

    able:While the primary purpose of medical research is

    to generatenew knowledge,this goalcannevertakepre-

    cedence over the rights and interests of individual re-

    search subjects (paragraph 8, emphasis added).

    Similarly, the declaration permits research com-

    binedwithmedicalcareanincreasingly important cat-

    egory of researchonlyto theextent that this is justi-

    fiedbyitspotentialpreventive, diagnosticor therapeutic

    value, leavingit unclearwhetherindividualsmay be ex-

    posedtoanynetrisksinthiscontext(paragraph14).Even

    morepuzzling,the declaration seemsto allow nonben-

    eficial research only with individuals who areunableto

    give informed consent (paragraph 28).

    Clearly, thegoalof generatingnew knowledgemustnot take precedence over the rights of individual re-

    searchparticipants.Researchparticipantsshould notbe

    exposedto highnet risks.Yetnonbeneficialresearchcan

    be ethical whenthe netrisks to participants interestsare

    lowand thebenefitsto society are sufficiently large. In-

    deed,inapparentconflictwithparagraphs8and14,para-

    graphs16and28seemtoaffirmthatethicalresearchcan

    pose some net risks to participants: Medical research

    involving human subjects mayonly be conductedif the

    importanceof theobjectiveoutweighsthe risksand bur-

    dens to the research subjects(paragraph 16).

    The declarations lack of clearand consistent guid-

    anceregardingwhen netrisks areacceptablecreates un-necessary confusion and fuels the unfounded concern

    that all medical research is inherently exploitative.

    ProblemsWithResearchinPoor Communities

    Thedeclarationrightlyrecognizes theimportance ofpro-

    tectingthe worst off, including populationswholack ac-

    cesstoadequatehealthcare.Thereviseddeclarationcalls

    forspecial protectionfor groupsand individualswhoare

    vulnerableandmayhaveanincreasedlikelihoodofbeing

    wrongedorofincurringadditionalharm(paragraph19).3

    VIEWPOINT

    Joseph Millum, PhDDepartmentof

    Bioethics, Clinical

    Center, National

    Institutesof Health,

    Bethesda, Maryland,

    and Fogarty

    International Center,

    National Institutesof

    Health, Bethesda,

    Maryland.

    David Wendler, PhD

    Departmentof

    Bioethics, Clinical

    Center, National

    Institutesof Health,

    Bethesda, Maryland.

    Ezekiel J.Emanuel,

    MD,PhD

    Officeof theProvost,

    Universityof

    Pennsylvania,

    Philadelphia, and

    Departmentof Medical

    Ethics and Health

    Policy, Perelman School

    of Medicine,University

    of Pennsylvania,

    Philadelphia.

    Viewpoint

    Related article

    Corresponding

    Author: Ezekiel J.

    Emanuel, MD,PhD,

    Departmentof Medical

    Ethics and Health

    Policy, Universityof

    Pennsylvania, 122

    CollegeHall,

    Philadelphia, PA19104

    (vp-global@upenn

    .edu).

    Opinion

    jama.com JAMA Published onlineOctober 19, 2013 E1

    wnloaded From: http://jama.jamanetwork.com/ by a Biblioteca Istituto Superiore di Sanit - Roma User on 11/19/2013

  • 7/26/2019 Dichiarazione Di Helsinki

    2/2

    It thendelineates 3 conditions for researchwith vulnerable groups:

    (1)theresearchmustberesponsivetotheirhealthneeds;(2)itmust

    be impossible to carry out with nonvulnerable groups; and (3) the

    group should stand to benefit fromthe knowledge, practices, or in-

    terventions thatresult fromthe research(paragraph 20).

    Thedeclarationis confusedand mistakenaboutvulnerability and

    appropriateprotections.4,5First,thegroupthedeclarationhasinmind

    that is in need of special protections is vulnerable because they arepoorand have limited access to medical services, notbecause they

    areat higher riskof harms. Failureto make thisclearunderminesthe

    protections. What is necessary to protect poor populations is very

    different from what is necessaryto protect participants whoare at

    higherrisk ofharm,cannot consent, or, becauseof their position,eg,

    being a student,are atincreased risk of coercion.

    Secondand moreimportantly,the declarationis confusedabout

    whatconstitutesappropriateprotections andthe appropriatemeans

    to achieve those protections.

    Tobe clearand comprehensive,the declaration should state that

    populations who are vulnerable to exploitation should always re-

    ceive a fair level of benefits. Providingfair benefits is thegoal.The

    means to achieve it vary. In only a limited number of clinical trials,

    the requirement that vulnerable groups should benefit from the

    knowledge, practice, or interventions that result from the re-

    search (paragraph 20) along with the requirement that partici-

    pants haveposttrial access to interventions identified as beneficial

    (paragraph 34) can provide fair benefits, but only with respect to

    phase 3 trialsin which an experimentalintervention is found to be

    more effective. When research does not prove an intervention ef-

    fectivephase 1 and 2, and negative phase 3 research trials

    participantsfrom poorcountrieswith limited access tomedicalser-

    vicesare unlikely to benefit at allfrom these requirements. In these

    cases, a research project might supply clean water, new clinics, or

    build local medical andresearch capacity. If this level of benefits is

    fair, then theresearchwill not be exploitative.

    ProblemsWithPlacebos

    Therevised declaration fails to address the testingof interventions

    thatmay be beneficialto some groups but are expected tobe less

    effective thaninterventionsthatare available elsewherethebest

    proven interventions. It asserts that placebos may be used only

    when thepatients whoreceive them will notbe subject to addi-

    tional risksof serious or irreversible harmasaresultofnotreceiving

    thebestproven intervention (paragraph33, emphasisadded). Howtointerpret this last clauseis unclear. Thedanger is that itmay pre-

    clude vital research that promises to improve the condition of the

    worst off. Forexample, pasttrialsof single-dose nevirapine given to

    mothersduringlabor andtheir infantswithin 72hours ofbirth dem-

    onstrated that this approach was a highly cost-effective means of

    reducing mother-to-child-transmission of HIV.6 However, it was

    known at the time that single-dose nevirapine would not be as ef-

    fective as more comprehensive and much more expensive treat-

    ment regimens that also targeted transmission during pregnancy.

    Yet trialsthat used less than thebest-knowntreatment were ethi-

    caland had thepotential tobenefit mothers whootherwise would

    receive nothing. A future and better declaration should allow such

    trials under strict conditions, especially when no patients are de-

    prived of treatment they would otherwise receive and the re-

    searchhas the potentialto save lives and improve thecare of poor

    populations.7

    Conclusion

    Therevised Declarationof Helsinkirepresents a significant improve-

    ment over previous versions. Creating an international document

    to guide research around the world is an enormously difficult and

    complicatedtask.Nevertheless,importantproblems andsomecon-

    fusion remain in this 50th-anniversary declaration. The definitive

    guidance on research ethics and even better protection for re-

    search participants await responsesto the Declaration of Helsinkis

    remaining challenges.

    ARTICLEINFORMATION

    Published Online: October 19,2013.

    doi:10.1001/jama.2013.281632.

    Conflict of Interest Disclosures: All authors have

    completedand submitted theICMJE Form for

    Disclosure of PotentialConflicts of Interest.Dr

    Emanuel reported receiving payment for speaking

    engagements unrelatedto this work.

    Disclaimer: Theviews expressedare the authors

    own. Theydo notrepresent thepositionor policy of

    the National Institutesof Health, US PublicHealth

    Service, or theDepartmentof Healthand Human

    Services.

    REFERENCES

    1. Moralscience:protectingparticipants in human

    subjects research. Presidential Commission for the

    Studyof Bioethical Issues. http://bioethics.gov/sites

    /default/files/Moral%20Science%20June

    %202012.pdf. Accessed October 9, 2013.

    2. Emanuel EJ.Reconsidering theDeclarationof

    Helsinki. Lancet. 2013;381(9877):1532-1533.

    3. HurstSA. Vulnerabilityin research andhealth

    care;describing theelephant in theroom?

    Bioethics. 2008;22(4):191-202.

    4. Participants in the2001 Conferenceon Ethical

    Aspects of Research in DevelopingCountries.Moral

    standards for research in developingcountries:

    from reasonableavailability to fairbenefits.

    Hastings CentRep. 2004;34(3):17-27.

    5. MillumJ. Sharing thebenefitsof research fairly:

    two approaches.J Med Ethics. 2012;38(4):219-223.

    6. MarseilleE, Kahn JG,MmiroF,et al.Cost

    effectiveness of single-dosenevirapine regimen for

    mothers and babiesto decrease vertical HIV-1

    transmissionin sub-Saharan Africa.Lancet.

    1999;354(9181):803-809.

    7. WendlerD, Emanuel EJ, LieRK. Thestandard of

    care debate: can research in developingcountries

    be both ethical andresponsiveto thosecountries

    health needs?Am J Public Health.

    2004;94(6):923-928.

    Opinion Viewpoint

    E2 JAMA Published online October 19, 2013 jama.com

    wnloaded From: http://jama.jamanetwork.com/ by a Biblioteca Istituto Superiore di Sanit - Roma User on 11/19/2013